This article is about the philosophical study of nature. For the current in 19th-century German idealism, see
Naturphilosophie.
A celestial map from the 17th century, by the Dutch cartographer Frederik De Wit
From the ancient world, starting with
Aristotle, to the 19th century, the term "natural philosophy" was the common term used to describe the practice of studying nature. It was in the 19th century that the concept of "science" received its modern shape with new titles emerging such as "biology" and "biologist", "physics" and "physicist" among other technical fields and titles; institutions and communities were founded, and unprecedented applications to and interactions with other aspects of society and culture occurred.
[1] Isaac Newton's book
Philosophiae Naturalis Principia Mathematica (1687), whose title translates to "Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy", reflects the then-current use of the words "natural philosophy", akin to "systematic study of nature". Even in the 19th century, a treatise by
Lord Kelvin and
Peter Guthrie Tait, which helped define much of modern physics, was titled
Treatise on Natural Philosophy (1867).
In the
German tradition,
naturphilosophie or nature philosophy persisted into the 18th and 19th century as an attempt to achieve a speculative unity of
nature and
spirit. Some of the greatest names in German philosophy are associated with this movement, including
Spinoza,
Goethe,
Hegel and
Schelling.
Origin and evolution of the term[edit]
The term
natural philosophy preceded our current
natural science (i.e. empirical science). Empirical science historically developed out of
philosophy or, more specifically, natural philosophy. Natural philosophy was distinguished from the other precursor of modern science,
natural history, in that natural philosophy involved reasoning and explanations about nature (and after
Galileo,
quantitative reasoning), whereas natural history was essentially
qualitative and descriptive.
In the 14th and 15th centuries, natural philosophy' was one of many branches of
philosophy, but was not a specialized field of study. The first person appointed as a specialist in Natural Philosophy
per se was
Jacopo Zabarella, at the
University of Padua in 1577.
Modern meanings of the terms
science and
scientists date only to the 19th century. Before that,
science was a synonym for
knowledge or
study, in keeping with its Latin origin. The term gained its modern meaning when
experimental science and the
scientific method became a specialized branch of study apart from natural philosophy.
[2]
From the mid-19th century, when it became increasingly unusual for scientists to contribute to both
physics and
chemistry, "natural philosophy" came to mean just
physics, and the word is still used in that sense in degree titles at the
University of Oxford. In general, chairs of Natural Philosophy established long ago at the oldest
universities, are nowadays occupied mainly by physics
professors. Isaac Newton's book
Philosophiae Naturalis Principia Mathematica (1687), whose title translates to "Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy", reflects the then-current use of the words "natural philosophy", akin to "systematic study of nature". Even in the 19th century, a treatise by
Lord Kelvin and Peter Guthrie Tait, which helped define much of modern physics, was titled
Treatise on Natural Philosophy (1867).
Scope of natural philosophy[edit]
In
Plato's earliest known dialogue,
Charmides distinguishes between
science or bodies of knowledge that produce a physical result, and those that do not. Natural philosophy has been categorized as a theoretical rather than a practical branch of philosophy (like ethics). Sciences that guide arts and draw on the philosophical knowledge of nature may produce practical results, but these subsidiary sciences (e.g., architecture or medicine) go beyond natural philosophy.
The study of natural philosophy seeks to explore the cosmos by any means necessary to understand the universe. Some ideas presuppose that change is a reality. Although this may seem obvious, there have been some philosophers who have denied the concept of metamorphosis, such as Plato's predecessor
Parmenides and later Greek philosopher
Sextus Empiricus, and perhaps some Eastern philosophers.
George Santayana, in his
Scepticism and Animal Faith, attempted to show that the reality of change cannot be proven. If his reasoning is sound, it follows that to be a physicist, one must restrain one's skepticism enough to trust one's senses, or else rely on
anti-realism.
René Descartes'
metaphysical system of
Cartesian Dualism describes two kinds of substance: matter and mind. According to this system, everything that is "matter" is
deterministic and natural—and so belongs to natural philosophy—and everything that is "mind" is
volitional and non-natural, and falls outside the domain of philosophy of nature.
Branches and subject matter of natural philosophy[edit]
History of natural philosophy[edit]
Humankind's mental engagement with nature certainly predates civilization and the record of history. Philosophical, and specifically non-religious thought about the natural world, goes back to ancient Greece. These lines of thought began before Socrates, who turned from his philosophical studies from speculations about nature to a consideration of man, viz., political philosophy. The thought of early philosophers such
Parmenides,
Heraclitus, and
Democritus centered on the natural world. Plato followed Socrates in concentrating on man. It was Plato's student, Aristotle, who, in basing his thought on the natural world, returned empiricism to its primary place, while leaving room in the world for man.
[3] Martin Heidegger observes that Aristotle was the originator of conception of nature that prevailed in the Middle Ages into the modern era:
The
Physics is a lecture in which he seeks to determine
beings that arise on their own,
τὰ φύσει ὄντα, with regard to their
being. Aristotelian "physics" is different from what we mean today by this word, not only to the extent that it belongs to antiquity whereas the modern physical sciences belong to
modernity, rather above all it is different by virtue of the fact that
Aristotle's "physics" is philosophy, whereas modern physics is a
positive science that presupposes a
philosophy.... This book determines the warp and woof of the whole of Western thinking, even at that place where it, as modern thinking, appears to think at odds with ancient thinking. But opposition is invariably comprised of a decisive, and often even perilous, dependence. Without Aristotle's
Physics there would have been no Galileo.
[4]
Aristotle surveyed the thought of his predecessors and conceived of nature in a way that charted a middle course between their excesses.
[5]
Plato's world of eternal and unchanging
Forms, imperfectly represented in matter by a divine
Artisan, contrasts sharply with the various mechanistic
Weltanschauungen, of which
atomism was, by the fourth century at least, the most prominent… This debate was to persist throughout the ancient world. Atomistic mechanism got a shot in the arm from
Epicurus… while the
Stoics adopted a
divine teleology… The choice seems simple: either show how a structured, regular world could arise out of undirected processes, or inject intelligence into the system. This was how Aristotle… when still a young acolyte of Plato, saw matters.
Cicero… preserves Aristotle's own
cave-image: if
troglodytes were brought on a sudden into the upper world, they would immediately suppose it to have been intelligently arranged. But Aristotle grew to abandon this view; although he believes in a divine being, the
Prime Mover is not the
efficient cause of action in the Universe, and plays no part in constructing or arranging it... But, although he rejects the divine Artificer, Aristotle does not resort to a pure mechanism of random forces. Instead he seeks to find a middle way between the two positions, one which relies heavily on the notion of Nature, or
phusis.
[6]
"The world we inhabit is an orderly one, in which things generally behave in predictable ways, Aristotle argued, because every natural object has a "nature"-an attribute (associated primarily with form)that makes the object behave in its customary fashion..."
[7]Aristotle recommended
four causes as appropriate for the business of the natural philosopher, or physicist, “and if he refers his problems back to all of them, he will assign the ‘why’ in the way proper to his science—the matter, the form, the mover, [and] ‘that for the sake of which’”. While the vagrancies of the material cause are subject to circumstance, the formal, efficient and final cause often coincide because in natural kinds, the mature form and
final cause are one and the same. The
capacity to mature into a specimen of one's kind is directly acquired from “the primary source of motion”, i.e., from one's father, whose seed (
sperma) conveys the essential nature (common to the species), as a hypothetical
ratio.
[8]
- Material cause
- An object's motion will behave in different ways depending on the [substance/essence] from which it is made. (Compare clay, steel, etc.)
- Formal cause
- An object's motion will behave in different ways depending on its material arrangement. (Compare a clay sphere, clay block, etc.)
- Efficient cause
- That which caused the object to come into being; an "agent of change" or an "agent of movement".
- Final cause
- The reason that caused the object to be brought into existence.
From the late Middle Ages into the modern era, the tendency has been to narrow "science" to the consideration of efficient or agency-based causes of a particular kind:
[9]
The action of an efficient cause may sometimes, but not always, be described in terms of quantitative force. The action of an artist on a block of clay, for instance, can be described in terms of how many pounds of pressure per square inch is exerted on it. The efficient causality of the teacher in directing the activity of the artist, however, cannot be so described…
The final cause acts on the agent to influence or induce her to act. If the artist works "to make money," making money is in some way the cause of her action. But we cannot describe this influence in terms of quantitative force. The final cause acts, but it acts according to the mode of final causality, as an end or good that induces the efficient cause to act. The mode of causality proper to the final cause cannot itself be reduced to efficient causality, much less to the mode of efficient causality we call "force."
[10]
Medieval philosophy of motion[edit]
Medieval thoughts on motion involved much of Aristotle's works
Physics and
Metaphysics. The issue that medieval philosophers had with motion was the inconsistency found between book 3 of
Physics and book 5 of
Metaphysics. Aristotle claimed in book 3 of
Physics that motion can be categorized by substance, quantity, quality, and place. where in book 5 of
Metaphysics he stated that motion is a magnitude of quantity. This disputation led to some important questions to natural philosophers: Which category/categories does motion fit into? Is motion the same thing as a terminus? Is motion separate from real things? These questions asked by medieval philosophers tried to classify motion.
[11]
William Ockham gives a good concept of motion for many people in the Middle Ages. There is an issue with the vocabulary behind motion which makes people think that there is a correlation between nouns and the qualities that make nouns. Ockham states that this distinction is what will allow people to understand motion, that motion is a property of mobiles, locations, and forms and that is all that is required to define what motion is. A famous example of this is
Occam's razor which simplifies vague statements by cutting them into more descriptive examples. "Every motion derives from an agent." becomes "each thing that is moved, is moved by an agent" this makes motion a more personal quality referring to individual objects that are moved.
[11]
Aristotle's philosophy of nature[edit]
-
-
- "An acorn is potentially, but not actually, an oak tree. In becoming an oak tree, it becomes actually what it originally was only potentially. this change thus involves passage from potentiality to actuality-not from nonbeing to being but from one kind or degree to being another"[7]
Aristotle held many important beliefs that started a convergence of thought for natural philosophy. Aristotle believed that attributes of objects belong to the objects themselves, and share traits with other objects that fit them into a category. He uses the example of dogs to press this point an individual dog (ex. one dog can be black and another brown) may have very specific attributes(ex. one dog can be black and another brown,) but also very general ones that classify it as a dog (ex. four legged). This philosophy can be applied to many other objects as well. This idea is different than that of Plato, with whom Aristotle had a direct association. Aristotle argued that objects have properties "form" and something that is not part of its properties "matter" that defines the object. The form cannot be separated from the matter. Giving the example that you can not separate properties and matter since this is impossible, you cannot collect properties in a pile and matter in another.
[7]
Aristotle believed that change was a natural occurrence. He used his philosophy of form and matter to argue that when something changes you change its properties with out changing its matter. This change happens but replacing certain properties with other properties. Since this change is always an intentional alteration whether by forced means or but natural ones, change is a controllable order of qualities. He argues that this happens through three categories of being; nonbeing, potential being, and actual being. through these three states the process of changing an object never truly destroys an objects forms during this transition state just blurs the reality between the two states. An example of this could be changing an object from red to blue with a transitional purple phase.
[7]
Other significant figures in natural philosophy[edit]
Early Greek Philosophers studied motion and the cosmos. Figures like
Hesiod regarded the Natural world as offspring of the gods, where others like
Leucippus and
Democritusregarded to world as lifeless atoms in a vortex.
Anaximander deduced that eclipses happen because apertures in rings of celestial fire.
Heraclitus believed that the heavenly bodies were made of fire that were contained within bowls, he thought that eclipses happen when the bowl turned away from the earth.
Anaximenes is believed to have stated that an underlying element was air, and by manipulating air someone could change its thickness to create fire, water, dirt, and stones.
Empedocles identified the elements that make up the world which he termed the roots of all things as Fire, Air. Earth, and Water.
Parmenides argued that all change is a logical impossibility. He gives the example that nothing can go from nonexistence to existence.
Plato argues that the world is an imperfect replica of an idea that a divine craftsman once held. He also believed that the only way to truly know something was through reason and logic not the study of the object its self, but that changeable matter is a viable course of study.
[7]
The
scientific method has ancient precedents and
Galileo exemplifies a mathematical understanding of nature which is the hallmark of modern natural scientists. Galileo proposed that objects falling regardless of their mass would fall at the same rate, as long as the medium they fall in is identical. The 19th-century distinction of a scientific enterprise apart from traditional natural philosophy has its roots in prior centuries. Proposals for a more "inquisitive" and practical approach to the study of nature are notable in
Francis Bacon, whose ardent convictions did much to popularize his insightful
Baconian method. The late 17th-century natural philosopher
Robert Boyle wrote a seminal work on the distinction between
physics and
metaphysics called,
A Free Enquiry into the Vulgarly Received Notion of Nature, as well as
The Skeptical Chymist, after which the modern science of
chemistry is named, (as distinct from
proto-scientific studies of
alchemy). These works of natural philosophy are representative of a departure from the
medievalscholasticism taught in European
universities, and anticipate in many ways, the developments which would
lead to science as practiced in the modern sense. As Bacon would say, "vexing nature" to reveal "her" secrets, (
scientific experimentation), rather than a mere reliance on largely historical, even
anecdotal,
observations of empirical
phenomena, would come to be regarded as a defining characteristic of
modern science, if not the very key to its success. Boyle's biographers, in their emphasis that he laid the foundations of modern chemistry, neglect how steadily he clung to the scholastic sciences in theory, practice and doctrine.
[12] However, he meticulously recorded observational detail on practical research, and subsequently advocated not only this practice, but its publication, both for successful and unsuccessful experiments, so as to validate individual claims by replication.
For sometimes we use the word
nature for that
Author of nature whom the
schoolmen, harshly enough, call
natura naturans, as when it is said that
nature hath made man partly corporeal and
partly immaterial. Sometimes we mean by the
nature of a thing the
essence, or that which the schoolmen scruple not to call the
quiddity of a thing, namely, the
attribute or
attributeson whose score it is what it is, whether the thing be
corporeal or not, as when we attempt to define the
nature of an
angel, or of a
triangle, or of a
fluid body, as such. Sometimes we take
nature for an internal principle of
motion, as when we say that a stone let fall in the
air is by
nature carried towards the centre of the
earth, and, on the contrary, that
fire or flame does
naturally move upwards toward
heaven. Sometimes we understand by
nature the established course of things, as when we say that
nature makes the
night succeed the
day,
nature hath made
respiration necessary to the
life of men. Sometimes we take
nature for an
aggregate of powers belonging to a body, especially a living one, as when
physicians say that
nature is strong or weak or spent, or that in such or such
diseases nature left to herself
will do the cure. Sometimes we take nature for the
universe, or system of the corporeal works of
God, as when it is said of a
phoenix, or a
chimera, that there is no such thing in
nature, i.e. in the world. And sometimes too, and that most commonly, we would express by
nature a
semi-deityor other strange kind of being, such as this discourse examines the notion of.
[13]
— Robert Boyle, A Free Enquiry into the Vulgarly Received Notion of Nature
The modern emphasis is less on a broad empiricism (one that includes passive observation of nature's activity), but on a narrow conception of the empirical concentrating on thecontrol exercised through experimental (active) observation for the sake of control of nature. Nature is reduced to a passive recipient of human activity.
Current work in natural philosophy[dubious – discuss][edit]
| This section requires expansion.(August 2011) |
Especially since the mid-20th-century European crisis, some thinkers argued the importance of looking at nature from a broad philosophical perspective, rather than what they considered a narrowly positivist approach relying implicitly on a hidden, unexamined philosophy.
[15] One line of thought grows from the Aristotelian tradition, especially as developed by
Thomas Aquinas. Another line springs from
Edmund Husserl, especially as expressed in
The Crisis of European Sciences. Students of his such as
Jacob Klein and
Hans Jonas more fully developed his themes. Last but not least, there is the
process philosophy inspired by
Alfred North Whitehead's works.
[16]
Among living scholars,
Brian David Ellis,
Nancy Cartwright,
David Oderberg, and
John Dupré are some of the more prominent thinkers who can arguably be classed as generally adopting a more open approach to the natural world. Ellis (2002) observes the rise of a "New Essentialism."
[17] David Oderberg (2007) takes issue with other philosophers, including Ellis to a degree, who claim to be essentialists. He revives and defends the Thomistic-Aristotelian tradition from modern attempts to flatten nature to the limp subject of the experimental method.
[18]