Wednesday, February 18, 2015

New Riddle of Induction



From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
"Grue and bleen" redirects here. For the linguistic term "grue", used for translation from natural languages, see Distinction of blue and green in various languages.
Grue and bleen are predicates coined by Nelson Goodman in Fact, Fiction, and Forecast to illustrate the "new riddle of induction". These predicates are unusual because their application to things is time dependent. For Goodman they illustrate the problem of projectable predicates and ultimately, which empirical generalizations are law-like and which are not.[1][2] Goodman's construction and use of grue and bleen illustrates how philosophers use simple examples in conceptual analysis.

Grue and bleen defined[edit]

Goodman defined grue relative to an arbitrary but fixed time t as follows:[note 1] An object is grue just in case it is observed before t and is green, or else is not so observed and is blue. An object is bleen just in case it is observed before t and is blue, or else is not so observed and is green.[3]
To understand the problem Goodman posed, it is helpful to imagine some arbitrary future time t, say January 1, 2025. For all green things we observe up to time t, such asemeralds and well-watered grass, both the predicates green and grue apply. Likewise for all blue things we observe up to time t, such as bluebirds or blue flowers, both the predicates blue and bleen apply. On January 2, 2025, however, emeralds and well-watered grass are now bleen and bluebirds or blue flowers are now grue. Clearly, the predicates grue and bleen are not the kinds of predicates we use in everyday life or in science, but the problem is that they apply in just the same way as the predicates greenand blue up until some future time t. From our current perspective (i.e., before time t), how can we say which predicates are more projectable into the future: green and blue orgrue and bleen?

The new riddle of induction[edit]

In this section, Goodman's new riddle of induction is outlined in order to set the context for his introduction of the predicates grue and bleen and thereby illustrate theirphilosophical importance.[2][4]

The old problem of induction and its dissolution[edit]

Goodman poses Hume's problem of induction as a problem of the validity of the predictions we make. Since predictions are about what has yet to be observed and because there is no necessary connection between what has been observed and what will be observed, what is the justification for the predictions we make? We cannot use deductive logic to infer predictions about future observations based on past observations because there are no valid rules of deductive logic for such inferences. Hume's answer was that our observations of one kind of event following another kind of event result in our minds forming habits of regularity (i.e., associating one kind of event with another kind). The predictions we make are then based on these regularities or habits of mind we have formed.
Goodman takes Hume's answer to be a serious one. He rejects other philosophers' objection that Hume is merely explaining the origin of our predictions and not their justification. His view is that Hume is on to something deeper. To illustrate this, Goodman turns to the problem of justifying a system of rules of deduction. For Goodman, the validity of a deductive system is justified by its conformity to good deductive practice. The justification of rules of a deductive system depends on our judgements about whether to reject or accept specific deductive inferences. Thus, for Goodman, the problem of induction dissolves into the same problem as justifying a deductive system and while, according to Goodman, Hume was on the right track with habits of mind, the problem is more complex than Hume realized.
In the context of justifying rules of induction, this becomes the problem of confirmation of generalizations for Goodman. However, the confirmation is not a problem of justification but instead it is a problem of precisely defining how evidence confirms generalizations. It is with this turn that grue and bleen have their philosophical role in Goodman's view of induction.

Projectable predicates[edit]

US government example for time dependent predicates: Before March 1797, arbitrarily many observations would support both version of the prediction "The US forces were always commanded by { George Washington
the   US   President
 }, hence they will be commanded by him in the future"
, which today is known as { false
true
 }, similar to "Emeralds were always { grue
green
 }, hence they will be so in the future"
.
The new riddle of induction, for Goodman, rests on our ability to distinguish lawlike from non-lawlike generalizations. Lawlike generalizations are capable of confirmation while non-lawlikegeneralizations are not. Lawlike generalizations are required for making predictions. Using examples from Goodman, the generalization that all copper conducts electricity is capable of confirmation by a particular piece of copper whereas the generalization that all men in a given room are third sons is not lawlike but accidental. The generalization that all copper conducts electricity is a basis for predicting that this piece of copper will conduct electricity. The generalization that all men in a given room are third sons, however, is not a basis for predicting that a given man in that room is a third son.
What then makes some generalization lawlike and other accidental? This, for Goodman, becomes a problem of determining which predicates are projectable (i.e., can be used inlawlike generalizations that serve as predictions) and which are not. Goodman argues that this is where the fundamental problem lies. This problem, known as Goodman's paradox, is as follows. Consider the evidence that all emeralds examined thus far have been green. This leads us to conclude (by induction) that all future emeralds will be green. However, whether this prediction is lawlike or not depends on the predicates used in this prediction. Goodman observed that (assuming t has yet to pass) it is equally true that every emerald that has been observed is grue. Thus, by the same evidence we can conclude that all future emeralds will be grue. The new problem of induction becomes one of distinguishing projectable predicates such as "green" and "blue" from non-projectable predicates such as "grue" and bleen.
Hume, Goodman argues, missed this problem. We do not, by habit, form generalizations from all associations of events we have observed but only some of them. Lawlikepredictions (or projections) ultimately are distinguishable by the predicates we use. Goodman's solution is to argue that Lawlike predictions are based on projectable predicates such as "green" and "blue" and not on non-projectable predicates such as "grue" and bleen and what makes predicates projectable is their entrenchment, which depend on their past use in successful projections. Thus, "grue" and "bleen" function in Goodman's arguments to both illustrate the new riddle of induction and to illustrate the distinction between projectable and non-projectable predicates via their relative entrenchment.

Responses[edit]

The most obvious response is to point to the artificially disjunctive definition of grue. The notion of predicate entrenchment is not required. Goodman, however, noted that this move will not work. If we take grue and bleen as primitive predicates, we can define green as "grue if first observed before t and bleen otherwise", and likewise for blue. To deny the acceptability of this disjunctive definition of green would be to beg the question.
Another proposed resolution of the paradox (which Goodman addresses and rejects) that does not require predicate entrenchment is that "x is grue" is not solely a predicate of x, but of x and a time t—we can know that an object is green without knowing the time t, but we cannot know that it is grue. If this is the case, we should not expect "x is grue" to remain true when the time changes. However, one might ask why "x is green" is not considered a predicate of a particular time t—the more common definition of green does not require any mention of a time t, but the definition grue does. As we have just seen, this response also begs the question because definition blue can be defined in terms of grueand bleen, which explicitly refer to time.[5]

Swinburne[edit]

Richard Swinburne gets past the objection that green be redefined in terms of grue and bleen by making a distinction based on how we test for the applicability of a predicate in a particular case. He distinguishes between qualitative and locational predicates. Qualitative predicates, like green, can be assessed without knowing the spatial or temporal relation of x to a particular time, place or event. Locational predicates, like gruecannot be assessed without knowing the spatial or temporal relation of x to a particular time, place or event, in this case whether x is being observed before or after time t. Although green can be given a definition in terms of the locational predicates grue and bleen, this is irrelevant to the fact that green meets the criterion for being a qualitative predicate whereas grue is merely locational. He concludes that if some x's under examination—like emeralds—satisfy both a qualitative and a locational predicate, but projecting these two predicates yields conflicting predictions, namely, whether emeralds examined after time tshall appear blue or green, we should project the qualitative predicate, in this case green.[6]

Carnap[edit]

Rudolf Carnap responded[7] to Goodman's 1946 article. Carnap's approach to inductive logic is based on the notion of degree of confirmation c(h,e) of a given hypothesis h by a given evidence e.[note 2] Both h and e are logical formulas expressed in a simple language L which allows for
  • multiple quantification ("for every x there is a y such that ..."),
  • unary and binary predicate symbols (properties and relations), and
  • an equality relation "=".
The universe of discourse consists of denumerably many individuals, each of which is designated by an own constant symbol; they should be best regarded as positions (e.g. space-time points) rather than extended physical bodies.[8] A state description is a (usually infinite) conjunction containing every possible ground atomic sentence, either negated or unnegated; such a conjunction describes a possible state of the whole universe.[9] Carnap requires the following semantic properties:
  • Atomic sentences must be logically independent of each other.[10] In particular, different constant symbols must designate different and entirely separate individuals.[note 3]Moreover, different predicates must be logically independent.[note 4][note 5]
  • The qualities and relations designated by the predicates must be simple, i.e. they must not be analyzable into simpler components.[11] Apparently, Carnap had in mind anirreflexivepartial, and well-founded[note 6] order[note 7] "is simpler than".
  • The set of primitive predicates in L must be complete, i.e. every respect in which two positions in the universe may be found to differ by direct observation, must be expressible in L.[12]
Carnap distinguishes three kinds of properties:
  1. Purely qualitative properties; that is, properties expressable without using individual constants, but not without primitive predicates,
  2. Purely positional properties; that is, properties expressable without primitive predicates, and
  3. Mixed properties; that is, all remaining expressable properties.
An example for 1., 2., and 3. is "x is blue or x is non-warm""x = a23", and "x is red and not x = a23", respectively, where x denotes a variable, and a23 denotes a constant.
Based on his theory of inductive logic sketched above, Carnap formalizes Goodman's notion of projectibility of a property W as follows: the higher the relative frequency of W in an observed sample, the higher is the probability that a non-observed individual has the property W. Carnap suggests "as a tentative answer" to Goodman, that all purely qualitative properties are projectible, all purely positional property are non-projectible, and mixed properties require further investigation.[13]

Quine[edit]

Willard Van Orman Quine discusses an approach to consider only "natural kinds" as projectable predicates.[14] He first relates Goodman's grue paradox to Hempel's raven paradox by defining two predicates F and G to be (simultaneously) projectible if all their shared instances count toward confirmation of the claim "each F is a G".[15] Then Hempel's paradox just shows that the complements of projectible predicates (such as "is a raven", and "is black") need not be projectible,[note 8] while Goodman's paradox shows that "is green" is projectible, but "is grue" is not.
Next, Quine reduces projectibility to the subjective notion of similarity. Two green emeralds are usually considered more similar than two grue ones if only one of them is green. Observing a green emerald makes us expect a similar observation (i.e., a green emerald) next time. Green emeralds are a natural kind, but grue emeralds are not. Quine investigates "the dubious scientific standing of a general notion of similarity, or of kind".[16] Both are basic to thought and language, like the logical notions of e.g. identity,negationdisjunction. However, it remains unclear how to relate the logical notions to similarity or kind;[note 9] Quine therefore tries to relate at least the latter two notions to each other.
Goodman's counter-example against a definition of "natural kind" based on Carnap
Failed attempt to define a kind as the set of all objects x that are more similar to a "paradigm" object p than p is to a "foil" object, in analogy to the definition of a circle area in geometry.
Relation between similarity and kind
Assuming finitely many kinds only, the notion of similarity can be defined by that of kind: an object A is more similar toB than to C if A and B belong jointly to more kinds[note 10] than A and C do.[17][note 11]
Vice versa, it remains again unclear how to define kind by similarity. Defining e.g. the kind of red things as the set of all things that are more similar to a fixed "paradigmatical" red object than this is to another fixed "foil" non-red object (cf. left picture) isn't satisfactory, since the degree of overall similarity, including e.g. shape, weight, will afford little evidence of degree of redness.[17] (In the picture, the yellow paprika might be considered more similar to the red one than the orange.)
An alternative approach inspired by Carnap defines a natural kind to be a set whose members are more similar to each other than each non-member is to at least one member.[18] [note 12] However, Goodman[19] argued, that this definition would make the set of all red round things, red wooden things, and round wooden things (cf. right picture) meet the proposed definition of a natural kind,[note 13] while "surely it is not what anyone means by a kind".[note 14][20]
While neither of the notions of similarity and kind can be defined by the other, they at least vary together: if A is reassessed to be more similar to C than to B rather than the other way around, the assignment of ABC to kinds will be permuted correspondingly; and conversely.[20]
Basic importance of similarity and kind
In language, every general term owes its generality to some resemblance of the things referred to. Learning to use a word depends on a double resemblance, viz. between the present and past circumstances in which the word was used, and between the present and past phonetic utterances of the word.[21]
Every reasonable expectation depends on resemblance of circumstances, together with our tendency to expect similar causes to have similar effects.[16] This includes any scientific experiment, since it can be reproduced only under similar, but not under completely identical, circumstances. Already Heraclitus' famous saying "No man ever steps in the same river twice" highlighted the distinction between similar and identical cirumstances.
Genesis of similarity and kind
In a behavioral sense, humans and other animals have an innate standard of similarity. It is part of our animal birthright, and characteristically animal in its lack of intellectual status, e.g. its alieness to mathematics and logic,[25] cf. bird example.
Induction itself is essentially animal expectation or habit formation. Ostensive learning[26] is a case of induction, and a curiously comfortable one, since each man's spacing of qualities and kind is enough like his neighbor's.[27] In contrast, the "brute irrationality of our sense of similarity" offers little reason to expect it being somehow in tune with the unanimated nature, which we never made.[note 15] Why inductively obtained theories about it should be trusted is the perennial philosophical problem of induction. Quine, following Watanabe,[28] suggests Darwin's theory as an explanation: if people's innate spacing of qualities is a gene-linked trait, then the spacing that has made for the most successful inductions will have tended to predominate through natural selection.[29] However, this cannot account for the human ability to dynamically refine one's spacing of qualities in the course of getting acquainted with a new area.[note 16]

Similar predicates used in philosophical analysis[edit]

Quus[edit]

In his book Wittgenstein on Rules and Private LanguageSaul Kripke proposed a related argument that leads to skepticism about meaning rather than skepticism about induction, as part of his personal interpretation (nicknamed "Kripkenstein" by some[30]) of the private language argument. He proposed a new form of addition, which he called quus, which is identical with "+" in all cases except those in which either of the numbers added are equal to or greater than 57; in which case the answer would be 5, i.e.:
x\text{ quus }y= \begin{cases} x+y & \text{for }x,y <57 \\[12pt] 5 & \text{for } x\ge 57 \text{  or  } y\ge57 \end{cases}
He then asks how, given certain obvious circumstances, anyone could know that previously when I thought I had meant "+", I had not actually meant quus. Kripke then argues for an interpretation of Wittgenstein as holding that the meanings of words are not individually contained mental entities.

No comments: